May 2018

The Meaning of Mutuality in Business

Published May 2015

Written by Colin Mayer CBE, Peter Moores Professor of Management Studies at Saïd Business School, University of Oxford as part of the Oxford Mars Economics of Mutuality partnership. View PDF version.
___

1. Introduction

“I have seriously considered how far a man is justified in giving away the heritage of his children and have come to the conclusion that my children will be all the better for being deprived of this money. Great wealth is not to be desired and in my experience it is more of curse than a blessing to the families that possess it.” [1]

So on 14 December 1900 George Cadbury, standing in front of the Friends Meeting House on the idyllic village green of Bournville near Birmingham with 370 cottages and five hundred acres of land around him, declared that he was giving away his wealth to the Bournville Village Trust. The aim of the Trust was “the amelioration of the conditions of the working class and labouring population”. [2]

The idea of social welfare and reform was just emerging at the end of the 19th century spurred on by the writings of John Ruskin. Ruskin argued for an ethical approach to economic transactions and said that with wealth comes a moral obligation by which profit is only legitimate if it does not harm the rest of society.

Inspired by what George and his brother Richard Cadbury had created Joseph Rowntree, another Quaker, fierce competitor of Cadbury in the chocolate business and author in 1901 of Poverty: A Study in Town Life, created New Earswick on 150 acres near to York. And others followed the Cadbury and Rowntree lead – James Reckitt in Hull, Ebenezer Howard in Letchworth in Hertfordshire and Henrietta Barnett in Hampstead Garden Suburb. Business was not just responding to social reform but shaping it and the societies within which it operated.

Meanwhile a less wholesome aspect of chocolate production was taking place off the coast of West Africa. At the beginning of the 19th century, the Portuguese had introduced cocoa into the islands of São Tomé and Príncipe. The climate and rich volcanic soils of the islands made them well suited to growing the crop and in 1900 Cadbury bought 45% of its beans from São Tomé and Príncipe. But the Portuguese had imported something else into the islands as well – slave labour. The Portuguese officially ended it in the 1870s but in 1901 the board of Cadbury became aware of its continued use on its estates.

On 26 September 1908 the London newspaper, the Standard, published an article accusing Cadbury of blatant hypocrisy, claiming that: “it is the monstrous trade in human flesh and blood against which the Quaker and Radical ancestors of Mr Cadbury thundered in the better days of England”. [3] The Cadbury board were aggrieved believing that they had done what they could to pressurize the Portuguese government “to put a stop to the conditions of slavery – not merely to wash our own hands of any connection with them” and that if they had withdrawn from the islands they would have lost the little influence they had over the Portuguese. [4] They sued the Standard for libel and on 29 November 1909 the case came to court. The jury found in favour of Cadbury but awarded damages of “one farthing” clearly unimpressed by how Cadbury had handled the slavery issue.

Was Cadbury a mutual business? Did the creation of the village of Bournville demonstrate a mutual approach to its employees? Did its concern about social reform reflect a mutual attitude towards business? Was its continuing sourcing from plantations that employed slave labour and its failure to effect social reform in West Africa a violation of mutuality?

The answer to all these questions is in some respects yes and in some respects no. In particular, the history of Cadbury exemplifies the distinctive features of mutuality.


2. What is Mutuality in Business?

On 28 July 1947, Forrest E. Mars wrote a note in which he set out his vision for Mars Incorporated. This was that Mars Incorporated should “promote a mutuality of service and benefits among its consumers, distributors, competitors, suppliers, governments, employees and shareholders”. He described this as “the total purpose for which the Company exists”. It has become one of the five guiding principles of the company along with quality, responsibility, efficiency and freedom.

The only question is what does it mean? In popular parlance, the term mutuality has a particular connotation. The Oxford English Dictionary describes the definition of “a mutual company” as being of U.S. origin dating back to 1784 in Pennsylvania “designating or relating to a financial institution (as a building society, insurance company, etc.) without capital stock, that is owned by its members who subscribe to a common fund from which claims, loans, etc., are paid, profits after deductions being shared between them”. In other words it is a form of ownership and sharing of the profits of the firm amongst its members that stands in contrast with a stock corporation.

The sharing of profits is clearly a crucial component of both Forrest Mars’ and the common concept of mutuality. But as it has come to be interpreted by the Mars Corporation, it has elements that are both more and less than the popular understanding. It is less in so far as with mutual ownership come rights to participate in the control of the organization that derive from voting as well as income claims. Mutuality as understood in Mars does not have these associated voting rights. The ownership of the company remains entirely in the hands of the family and voting control therefore is solely restricted to the family. However, the company attaches immense importance to the participation of its employees in all aspects of decision taking and regards consultation and consensus as being core to its modus operandi as reflected in the term “associates” to describe its employees.

At the same time, Mars perceives mutuality as more than its common interpretation in so far as it extends beyond being just a legal form to encompass the notion of flourishing of both the organization and the individuals who are associated with it. This perhaps comes closest to Forrest Mars’ concept – the mutual flourishing of the company and all those associated in one form or another with it.

Furthermore, and this is where the concept as it is understood in the Mars context has perhaps the greatest insight, the two forms of flourishing are mutually reinforcing – the flourishing of the company is conducive to that of the individuals associated with it and the flourishing of the individuals associated with the company promotes the company itself. It is in other words reflexive between legal form and the human participants.

There is not only a belief that mutuality is conducive to these reinforcing benefits but that it is necessary – without it businesses will not flourish. It is not sufficient in so far as there are at least four other principles of quality, responsibility, efficiency and freedom that are of importance but it is at least one of if not the most important of the five principles.

What if anything is the underlying basis of this notion of mutuality – sharing to the benefit of those who share in the benefits and to the benefit of the company that does the sharing? The next section places the concept in the context of an economic and business perspective of the organization to explore its basis and validity.


3. A Framework of Analysis

The firm is conventionally regarded as a production function of different forms of inputs – capital, labour, land and materials – and a nexus of contracts that binds these different parties to the firm together with their customers and suppliers. Figure 1 illustrates this in the context of where there are two factors of production – capital (K) and labour (L) – and two parties – the owners (O) of the capital and the workers (W). The owners combine the capital that they possess and do not give to the workers with the labour that workers supply them to produce output Qo. The workers combine the labour they do not supply to the firm with the capital that the owners have given them to produce their own entrepreneurial output Qw. The figure shows the combination of capital and labour that allow the workers and owners to achieve particular levels of output Qw and Qo respectively with the origins of the output of the two groups (Ow and Oo) in the opposite quadrants of the diagram.

The owners are rich in capital but poor in labour skills. The workers are rich in labour but without capital. They are currently both at point A (autarky) on the diagram. There are therefore “gains from trade” in the sense that both parties can achieve higher levels of output and in particular achieve Pareto efficient outcomes along the line BB’ (the “best” outcomes) where the output of one party is maximized subject to a particular level of output of the other. Conventional theory suggests that market prices exist that sustain a point on this efficient frontier.

The problem that arises and that the owners and workers seek to resolve is whether the two parties can commit to deliver outcomes that are superior to autarky let alone Pareto optimality. Take for example the point B’ which is the Pareto efficient outcome that is most favourable to the workers W. This involves the owners providing capital Kw in return for workers supplying labour (Lw – Lw ) to the firm, keeping Lw2 for their own entrepreneurial activities. This allows the workers to achieve an output of Qw , which is in excess of their output Qw in autarky at A.

The problem is that by defaulting on their promise to supply (Lw – Lw ) and combining the capital Kw with all their labour supply Lw , they can achieve a higher level of output still of Qw . That will push the owners’ output down to Qo , which is below their level of output Qo2 in autarky. Anticipating this, the owners will refuse to give the workers the capital Kw , leaving everybody in the position of autarky, A. This is illustrative of how choice that adversely affects other parties is a burden of the human condition that has afflicted mankind since Adam and Eve in the Garden of Eden.

The workers need a way of being able to commit to supply labour. There are two possibilities. The first is that the workers put up a bond as surety for the capital and the supply of their labour and suppose that bond is worth Kw. In that case the owners know that in the event of the workers defaulting they can recover Kw . They will therefore be willing to supply that amount of capital in return for the workers supplying (Lw – Lw ), allowing point D to be reached yielding the same level of output as in autarky for the owners and Qw2 for the workers from their entrepreneurial activities. This is not as much as their output at B’ but more than at A.

What happens if, as may well be the case, the workers have nothing that they can offer as a bond? In that case a second possibility is that the owners can withdraw up to Kw1 of the capital they supply in the event of the workers defaulting on their promised supply of (Lw – Lw ). That would pull the workers entrepreneurial output back to autarky Qw . By offering the workers more than the output that they can achieve in autarky, Qw, the threat of losing their profit Qw – Qw encourages honesty on the part of the workers.

This does not work in the absence of a surplus accruing to the workers. If the workers had been required by the owners to supply labour Lw – Lw in return for capital Kw1 to reach point C and the same output as in autarky namely Qw1 then the threat of removing capital as a consequence of them failing to supply their promised labour leaves them in the same position as if they had supplied the labour. There is no punishment associated with the threat of removing capital in the absence of the workers earning a profit. Profit is an inducement to honesty.

The same holds in reverse for the owners. If there is a risk of the owners defaulting on their promise to supply capital Kw1 allowing them to achieve point H instead of D and output Qo7 then the threat of withdrawing labour will merely push the owners’ output back to autarky Qo2 at A, the same as at D. There is no punishment associated with default if workers were in any event extracting the entire surplus. However, if the workers were offering labour of (Lw – Lw ) then they can impose a loss of (Qo – Qo ) on the owners by withdrawing their labour and returning to autarky. So the workers can induce honesty on the part of the owners by sharing profits with them. Together the observations on workers and owners mean that profit is not just an inducement to honesty but the mutual sharing of profit is a mutual inducement to honesty.

This points to two observations. The first is that in the absence of the ability of parties to post bonds then profit is essential to the promotion of honesty and the avoidance of default. Second that in a reciprocal arrangement, which relies on the honesty of more than one party, then mutual sharing of profit is required to promote productive relationship between the two parties. The mutual sharing of profits is central to the generation of profits that in turn are critical to mutual arrangements.

Third, if one party can post a bond and the other cannot then the party that is unable to post a bond should receive a majority of the surplus as an inducement to honesty on their part which the other party can assure through the bond. So for example, if owners have collateral that they can post as bonds and workers do not then the distribution should be closer to point D than point C. In essence, current distributions of profits are determined by past accumulations with allocations to those with small accumulations being justified not just on fairness but also on efficiency criteria.


4. Conclusions

With this as a framework, let us conclude by applying it to the questions that were posed about Cadbury at the end of section 1. First, if Cadbury built Bournville without any anticipated reciprocal benefit to Cadbury’s commercial activities, it was operating at point E or G on Figure 1. This is not a mutual arrangement but pure philanthropy. If Cadbury anticipated a corresponding input of labour associated with at least points D or B’ then this might have been used to encourage a dedicated workforce that risked losing its benefits if it failed to meet its employers’ expectations.

Second if social reform and the responsibility of owners were perceived to be important then the distribution of profits to owners at points C and B could be viewed as part of the inducement to responsible conduct. In other words, workers forgo a significant share of profits in return for a commitment on the part of owners to supply the capital that is required to maintain economic activity. If that commitment can come from posting past accumulated capital as a bond then a larger share of profits can accrue to workers as an inducement to honesty on their part.

Finally, the failure of Cadbury to sustain human rights in Africa pushed them to an exploitative position at F. Cadbury had a particular responsibility to ensure that minimum standards of human rights were upheld in regard to workers who were not able to withdraw their labour as slaves. Cadbury therefore seriously violated principles of mutuality by allowing conditions at F to prevail.

This framework should therefore assist in understanding what is meant by the notion of mutuality, its significance in promoting economic activity and the factors that influence the appropriate sharing of benefits in a mutual relationship.

economics_of_mutuality_89.jpg___[1] Cited in Deborah Cadbury (2010), Chocolate Wars – From Cadbury to Kraft: 220 Years of Sweet Success and Bitter Rivalry, London: Harper Collins, p 176
[2] Ibid, p 176
[3] Id., p 213
[4] Id., p 214

Share
EmailLinkedIn

Other Articles

Jun 2024
Lisbon Conscious Business Education Conference 2024: Evolving Education for Ethical Business Practices 
Mar 2024
Nordic Economics of Mutuality Forum October 15-16

The first Economics of Mutuality forum to be held in Scandinavia, this event taking place October 15-16, 2024 will be hosted by Brandinnova, the Center for Brand Research at the Norwegian School of Economics (NHH), Jæren Sparebank, and the Economics of Mutuality Foundation.

Mar 2024
Oxford Virtual Executive Education Program, September 12 – October 31, 2024

Driving Impact Through Mutual Value Creation, an 8-week online course brought to you by Oxford University’s Saïd Business School and the Economics of Mutuality team, will equip you to walk the talk of Stakeholder Capitalism.

Mar 2024
Asia Economics of Mutuality Forum 24-25 April 2024

Korean and global leaders in business, academia, government, and civil society will gather at Hanyang University in Seoul, South Korea, to launch the inaugural Economics of Mutuality Foundation and Hanyang University’s Global Forum on the role of business and investing in society. The event will take place from April 24 to 25, 2024. The two-day event will include addresses by Professor Colin Mayer, former Dean of Oxford University’s Said Business School; Chairman Moon Kook Hyun, President of the New Paradigm Institute and former CEO of Yuhan-Kimberly, and Dr. Jay Jakub, the Executive Director of the Economics of Mutuality Foundation, and co-author of the book, “Completing Capitalism.” The event will highlight the roles of academia, corporations, investors, family offices and entrepreneurs in creating an ecosystem of mutual value co-creation by how companies deploy their capital in society.